O debate Ratziner e Habermas
Fe e razão
Etica comum e politeismo valoral
=====================================
Habermas vs the Pope
The
darling of the 68ers and Benedict XVI find a surprising amount to agree
on. Left-wing German philosopher Jürgen Habermas treats religion with
respect.
On
19th January last year, two old men came to the Catholic Academy of
Bavaria to debate the imposing-looking topic: “Pre-political moral
foundations of the liberal state.” Both are German; both grew up under
the third reich; both went on to achieve distinction in their respective
fields. But here the resemblance ends. Jürgen Habermas is a leftist
philosopher and advocate of “democratically enlightened common sense.”
His championship of untrammelled debate as the foundation of political
legitimacy has inspired radicals across the world. His antagonist,
Cardinal Ratzinger, came to prominence as an enforcer of doctrinal
orthodoxy throughout the Catholic church. He is now Pope Benedict XVI.
Here,
then, were the makings of an epic duel, worthy to stand alongside
Luther’s famous confrontation with Zwingli or Heidegger’s 1929 dispute
with Cassirer at Davos. But the duel never took place. The transcript of
the debate instead reveals the strange spectacle of philosopher and
cardinal bending over backwards to accommodate each other. Habermas
treats religious communities with great respect, claiming that they have
“preserved intact something which has elsewhere been lost.” And
Ratzinger grants a central role to the “divine light of reason” in
controlling the “pathologies of religion.”
This
conciliatory tone will come as a particular surprise to English
readers. Here, the periodic spectacle of “science versus religion” has
acquired something of the character of a Punch and Judy show. (See
Richard Dawkins’s Prospect piece on “Gerin oil.”) Things are different
in Germany. There, the long tradition of Kulturprotestantismus—a
diffuse, non-denominational religiosity—guarantees the churches
widespread respect, if not attendance. The German philosophers, although
rarely conventionally pious, always took religion seriously. Not for
them the sneering scepticism of Hume or Russell. Habermas is in this
tradition. Like Kant and Adorno, his aim is to disentangle religion’s
ethical vision from its dogmatic claims.
Habermas
has not abandoned his belief in the moral autonomy of the liberal
state, however. The democratic process generates its own grounds of
allegiance; it does not feed off a pre-political ethnic or religious
solidarity. This is what Habermas has famously termed “constitutional
patriotism.” For the German people, cut off from their own pre-war
cultural traditions, the concept of constitutional patriotism is a
godsend. It suggests the possibility of a civic pride purged of history.
The new parliamentary buildings in Berlin, chastely functional yet with
a certain subdued splendour, are a fitting monument to this renovated
German spirit.
But
how does religion fit into the gleaming new world of constitutional
patriotism? Here Habermas’s thinking takes a surprising turn. In the
face of the uprooting effects of technology and the global market, the
liberal state should “treat with care all cultural sources on which the
normative consciousness and solidarity of citizens draws.” Religion is
pre-eminent among such sources. “In sacred writings and religious
traditions, intuitions of sin and redemption, of deliverance from a life
experienced as unholy, have been articulated, subtly spelt out and kept
alive through interpretation over millennia.” Thus although the civic
bond is not based upon pre-existing religious ties, it should treat them
with the greatest delicacy, recognising them as important allies in its
own struggle against the alienating forces of the modern world.
Religious
insights become available to the secular world through a process of
what Habermas calls “saving translation.” Thus the Biblical vision of
man as made in the “image and likeness” of God finds a profane
expression in the principle of the equal worth of all human beings. Such
translations are not—as Habermas himself has admitted—always
successful. “When sin was converted to culpability, and the breaking of
divine commands to an offence against human laws, something was lost.”
This unpurged residue continues to haunt the secular imagination,
finding a garbled outlet in horror films and tabloid headlines. But even
if imperfect, the translation of religious into secular language still
remains our best hope of avoiding the savage conflicts that so often
beset the passage of modernity.
Ratzinger’s
presentation contains even more surprises than Habermas’s. Maybe the
former cardinal is simply presenting what Germans would call his
Schokoladenseite (“chocolatey” or sweet side), but the impression is of a
humane intellectual, not the dogmatist sometimes portrayed in the
liberal press. This should be no surprise. The Catholic church has
always been more open to the varieties of wisdom than orthodox
Protestantism. Thus while Habermas makes his peace with religion,
Ratzinger bestows his blessing on the modern multicultural state.
Significant
differences remain, of course. Ratzinger is less friendly to democracy
than Habermas. Popular support does not constitute legitimacy, he notes,
for majorities can be blind or wicked. What we need is a standard of
justice that transcends the “play of majorities.” Such a standard is
provided by natural law. Although associated with Catholic philosophy,
the doctrine of natural law does not rest upon specifically Christian
foundations. It appeals to human nature; it comprises that body of
principles binding on all humans in virtue of their membership of the
species. First developed by classical philosophers, natural law was only
later given a Christian inflection. Now, argues Ratzinger, it should be
restored to its original cosmopolitan breadth. Discussion of natural
law “must today be conceived and pursued interculturally. For
Christians, it would have to do with the creation and the creator. In
the Indian world, this might correspond to the concept of ‘Dharma,’ the
inner lawfulness of being; in the Chinese tradition to the idea of the
ordinances of heaven.”
However,
one serious difficulty stands in the way of this cosy cultural
convergence. Natural law theory presupposes a concept of nature which,
although not specifically Christian, is nonetheless theistic or
metaphysical in inspiration. It rests, that is to say, upon the premise
that nature provides us with rational grounds for action. And this view
of nature has—as Ratzinger himself admits—long since fallen victim to
evolutionary theory. If we are not creatures of God, but merely clever
monkeys, then how can the accidents of our constitution dictate what we
ought to do and be? Ratzinger’s response is to subject science itself to
a certain critical limitation. It is philosophy’s task, he claims, to
“keep open a view of the whole, of the broader dimensions of human
reality, of which only partial aspects can ever be revealed in science.”
How
can we account for this détente between the philosopher of radical
democracy, the darling of Germany’s 68ers, and a figure viewed by many
as the apotheosis of reaction? The spectre of religious terrorism offers
a partial explanation. In a 2001 lecture, Habermas described 9/11 as a
reaction to “an accelerated and radically uprooting modernisation.” If
the modern west is to be perceived as more than merely “godless,” if it
is to inspire not just fear, but also respect, it must recover its
ethical substance. And this in turn demands some kind of reconciliation
with its own religious inheritance.
But
Habermas’s deeper anxiety concerns genetic technology—the most menacing
example of “radically uprooting modernisation.” He has argued
repeatedly that the new “liberal eugenics” threatens the main assumption
upon which the liberal state is built: that of symmetrical relations
between free and equal citizens. Although his position does not rest
upon theological premises, he acknowledges its debt to the
Judeo-Christian view of life as a divine gift, immune to human
manipulation. Here is an instance of that “saving translation” discussed
above. The image of divine creation corresponds, in secular terms, to
the unpredictability of our genetic make-up—an unpredictability which
places absolute limits on the power of any one human being over another.
Ratzinger,
for his part, engages in some “saving translation” of his own. Shunning
conventional Catholic language of souls and essences, he accuses gene
technology of a “fundamental transformation of man’s attitude to
himself. He is no longer a gift of nature or the Creator; he is his own
product.”
Anxiety
over genetic technology is widespread in Germany, where it evokes
memories of Nazi breeding programmes. But the root of the disquiet lies
deeper. Germany’s tradition of ethical idealism encourages a sensitivity
to religious perspectives lacking in Britain’s more utilitarian public
culture. Here, the debate over gene technology has been dominated by
practical questions of health and economics. Principled objections are
to be appeased or pacified; it never occurs to us that they might
contain a point of general philosophical value. We in Britain have much
to learn from these two old men in Bavaria.
by Edward Skidelsky; November 20, 2005
O debate Kelsen e Maritain